Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Armed Groups

Written by

First of all I would like to extend a huge thank you to EJIL:Talk! for hosting this book discussion and to the three discussants for taking the time to read the book and to provide their comments. It is a privilege, and I look forward to the debate.

Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Armed Groups’ looks at the legal and practical mechanics of how international human rights law can be applied to armed groups. I focus on two key issues: (1) what is the legal basis for the application of international human rights law obligations to armed groups, and under what circumstances will the law apply, and (2) how will the application of human rights law to armed groups work in practice, noting that armed groups are definitely not States – and so cannot reasonably be subject to the same obligations – and also that significant variation exists amongst armed groups and so obligations may need to be applied to different armed groups in a different manner.

In this introductory post I would like to briefly set out why armed groups should be subject to human rights obligations, and to present an overview of my approach in relation to the two issues identified above.

Today, non-State armed groups exert significant influence over the lives of millions of people around the world. Indeed, at its height the Islamic State was reported as exercising governmental authority over up to 10 million people in Iraq and Syria, while the impact of other groups such as the CPN-M in Nepal, the LTTE in Sri Lanka, the FARC in Colombia, the Naxalites in India, or the BRN-C in Southern Thailand is well documented. The activity of these groups is demonstrably of international concern. Yet their activities are not subject to effective regulation.

For those armed groups party to a non-international armed conflict, the law of armed conflict (international humanitarian law) does establish certain rules, but these rules are primarily concerned with the conduct of hostilities, and negative obligations towards affected individuals (such as the prohibition of torture, or certain detention rules). These limited rules do not apply to armed groups not party to an armed conflict, such as the Urabenos in Colombia, or Boko-Haram prior to mid-2013.

This means that international law does not regulate the relationship between armed groups and individuals subject to their control or influence. International law does not establish how armed groups should treat these individuals, or how armed groups should govern areas subject to their control or influence. The result is a legal vacuum whereby armed groups are free to act as they wish, and there is no effective protection accorded to individuals’ (inalienable) human rights. Building on Andrew Clapham’s landmark work, this book suggests that human rights law offers a solution. But, if the law is to be developed in this area, both the legal basis for its application and how that application can work in practice must be clarified.

With respect to the establishment of a legal basis, the book examines how international law could be applied to armed groups that are either party or not party to a non-international armed conflict. This required looking at the concept of international legal personality, and it was concluded that if international law is to be applied to an armed group, then that armed group must (a) exist independently and (b) be sufficiently organised to that it can impose its will on its members.

For armed groups, this organisational capacity can be demonstrated by the existence of (some form of) a command structure capable of enforcing internal discipline. The independence criterion will be satisfied in situations in which the State cannot reasonably impose its will: at this point the authority of the State is displaced and the armed group exists independently of any superior authority. Independence is clearly established when an armed group becomes party to a non-international armed conflict (through satisfaction of the intensity requirement). Outside armed conflict, independence is most clearly established when an armed group exerts stable territorial control to the exclusion of the State, but an armed group may also exist independently in more complex situations. It is frequently noted, for example, that the State may rule by day, but the armed group by night. In situations such as these it is the armed group’s ability to exert control to the exclusion of the State that is relevant, and not the precise contours of that control. As such, the displacement of State authority may be demonstrated by an armed group’s ability to engage in certain activity – such as the commission of internationally prohibited acts – coupled with the State’s inability to reasonably impose its will.

The de facto control theory, and related concepts such as the principle of effectiveness and the ‘implied mandate’ are then used to demonstrate how international law applies to armed group’s that satisfy these organisational and independence criteria. Ratione personae restrictions associated with international human rights law are addressed, and overcome, by reference to the maintenance of the vertical authority relationship envisaged by international human rights law (the armed group is displacing the State), the international law of treaty interpretation, and the object and purpose of international human rights law.

Turning to how international human rights law obligations can be applied to armed groups, the key concern is that the reality of armed groups be taken into account. In this regard it is noted that armed groups are not States (differing in their legal rights and entitlements), and that even amongst armed groups themselves significant differences exist in relation to capacity and the extent of influence exercised. As such, it would be inappropriate to apply human rights to armed groups in a ‘one size fits all’ manner and so a context-dependent graduated approach is proposed, whereby obligations can be progressively applied to armed groups, in keeping with the extent to which they have displaced State authority. In order to regulate the application of obligations, an adapted form of the ‘respect, protect, fulfil’ framework is proposed.

Under this framework armed groups are initially subject to the obligation to respect, then the obligation to fulfil – broken down into its facilitate, provide and promote components – and finally the obligation to protect. Armed groups that have effectively displaced State authority and who exercise exclusive control over a territory and population, such as the LTTE, are therefore subject to significantly greater human rights obligations than a guerrilla group at the initial stages of insurgency, such as the BRN-C.

At the initial stage of obligation all armed groups bound by international human rights law are subject to the obligation to respect. As a primarily, although not exclusively, negative obligation, the obligation to respect can be satisfied by all armed groups possessing international legal personality; indeed, the obligations imposed on armed groups at this stage of gradation are similar to those imposed on armed groups party to a non-international armed conflict. As the group develops and displaces the State to an increasing extent, it is subject to the obligation to fulfil, and its sub-components the obligation to fulfil (provide), fulfil (facilitate) and fulfil (promote). Initially, it is likely that the obligation to facilitate will be most directly relevant to armed groups, given the reduced resources required to satisfy this obligation when compared to the obligation to provide. For example, if there is a medical emergency or epidemic in an area subject to the control of the armed group, and the group does not have the resources to provide direct medical assistance (obligation to provide), then the obligation to facilitate requires that the group ensure affected individuals’ rights by facilitating the provision of medical care by the State or third party organisations, such as the ICRC, MSF, or the WHO. In this instance, merely satisfying the obligation to respect would be insufficient as it would be incapable of ensuring the affected populations’ rights.

Satisfaction of the obligation to fulfil requires a balancing of the underlying provide, facilitate and promote components. The means by which the right is fulfilled is left to the discretion of the armed group. In certain situations it may be permissible for the armed group to fulfil a right solely by means of the obligation to facilitate, thereby reducing the overall resource constraints imposed on the group. This is not problematic: it is the protection of individuals’ rights that is important, and not the specific means by which they are secured. However, the obligations to provide and facilitate are interdependent means of securing the overall obligation to fulfil, and  although an armed group is granted certain discretion this cannot be abused in order to abdicate responsibility: if an armed group does not, or cannot, satisfy the obligation to provide, it must satisfy the obligation to facilitate, and vice versa.

The obligation to protect requires that the armed group protect individuals from threats to their rights posed by third parties: it relates to issues of public order and the rule of law, and to the regulation of the life of the affected population. Both the preventive and remedial components of the obligation to protect require some form of legislative authority. The armed group must promulgate rules so that individuals can regulate their behaviour, and detention and prosecution may be necessary if these rules are violated. This means that the application of the obligation to protect to armed groups must be restricted to those groups who have displaced State authority and exercise exclusive control over a territory and population.

The proposed gradated approach is facilitated by the territorial State’s continuing obligations with respect to the entirety of its national territory, including those areas where its authority has been effectively displaced. Accordingly, while armed groups may be subject to a limited number of human rights obligations in a given context, the State’s continuing obligations avoids a vacuum in protection vis-à-vis the remaining rights. The result is a ’division’ of obligations between the State and the armed group. Although the concept of subjecting States to continuing obligations in armed group territory may appear disingenuous at first glance, such activity is actually relatively routine. For instance, both the Indian and Sri Lankan State continued to provide services in areas controlled by the Naxalites and the LTTE respectively, while the Iraq and Syrian Governments continued to pay the salaries of oil and gas workers in Islamic State-controlled areas.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

Leave a Comment

Comments for this post are closed

Comments

Kriangsak Kittichaisaree says

November 2, 2016

Daragh,

Thanks for your commendable suggestions. My thought is as follows. When non-State armed groups operate in areas where the central Govt. can enforce national law to uphold human rights (e.g., the right to life) then any violations of such rights by any person are subject to criminal sanctions by the State. If non-State armed groups operate in areas where the central Govt. has no effective control or where the State in question is a failed State, the international community must ensure that there be no impunity/immunity/statute of limitations for those members of the groups who have abused human rights but who have now assumed power to govern that State. This is how, in practice, we can protect human rights for all vis-a-vis non-State armed groups.

Veronika Bilkova says

November 2, 2016

Dear Daragh,

Many thanks for kicking off what will certainly be a very interesting debate. Your argument, as I see it, is quite complex and it is obvious that in the short introductory piece you could not present it in an exhaustive manner. For those of us not so fortunate to have already read your book (those like me), further clarifications on some points would be useful. So if you allow me, I will raise a couple of these points and my apologies in advance if I ask about something which is clearly explained in the book.

First, I must admit I am somewhat confused by the concept of non-state armed groups (NSAG) you have introduced. The concept of armed (opposition) groups (AOG) is well established under international law, mainly IHL. Yet, since NSAG can also exist in time of peace, it is surely not just a new term for AOG. Some NSAG take part in a conflict, some do not. Some control a part of territory, some do not. Some fight for political purposes, others are criminal gangs. What is it that they all share and that makes them into a specific category? The fact that they are independent and organized clearly is not this characteristic feature, because other non-state actors (NGOs, TNCs) can meet it as well. The fact that they are armed does not help either, as, again, this might be true for other NSAs (PMSCs) too. So, what is it?

Secondly, you start your piece by explaining why in your view NSAG should be subject to human rights obligations. You argue that there is “a legal vacuum whereby armed groups are free to act as they wish”. And that HRL should full in this vacuum. I have doubts about both these claims.

Is there really a legal vacuum? As you rightly note, NSAG taking part in an armed conflict would be covered by IHL rules (Common Article 3, possibly APII, some Hague law, customary rules). It is true that, as you say, these rules are primarily concerned with negative obligations towards affected individuals and the conduct of hostilities. Yet, they clearly apply to all individuals in the power of any party to the conflict and the set of obligations they impose (especially if APII is applicable) is not so minimal. In times of peace, NSAG exercising territorial control would most probably be subject to the rules applicable to de facto regimes. So under what circumstances or in which areas exactly are NSAG “free to act as they wish”?

I also wonder why, provided there is that vacuum (or some gaps), it is HRL (and not, for instance, more IHL) that should fill it. What would be the added value of having HRL applicable to NSAG, apart from the symbolic side?
Would it be the content of the rules? You write that a context-dependent graduated approach would be used, in which NSAG not controlling any territory – that is, most NSAG – would only have the obligation to respect (ie. negative obligations, which they already seem to have under IHL anyway).
Would it be a simple and clear-cut nature of rules? Prima facie, this “graduated approach” looks pretty complicated to me.
Or would it be the enforcement mechanism? That is a chronical weakness of IHL but in your piece (I guess it is different in your book) you do not explain, who-how-in what procedure would enforce HR obligations of NSAs.

I would have other questions but I know I have already by far exceeded the standard length of a decent discussion comment, so I will stop here.

I really look forward to the debate and I hope that my questions will get answered in its course.

Marion Vironda Dubray says

November 2, 2016

Dear Daragh,

Thank you for sharing with us your analysis of this exciting issue.

Not having read (yet) your book, please excuse me if I ask you questions that have already been dealt with.

I would like to know your thoughts about armed groups' human rights obligations during and after transition from conflict where serious violations of international humanitarian law and gross violations of human rights have been committed.

Taking the case of an armed group "surviving" through the transition and still complying with the requirement you mentionned. Could/should such armed group be required to put in place transitional justice mechanisms, in order to fulfill victim's right to truth and right to justice?

I thank you in advance for answering my question and I am looking forward to reading your thoughts.

Best regards,

Marion Vironda Dubray

Daragh Murray says

November 3, 2016

Dear Veronika, Kriangsak

Thank you for your comments, and for taking the time. Just to address some of your points quite briefly.

The distinguishing factors of the armed groups addressed in the book are their independence and organisation. Organisation as a factor indicating ability to implement international law obligations – as you note a number of entities satisfy this – and independence. When I refer to independence it is not just to signify that the armed group is a non-State entity, but to indicate that it is also independent of the State, in that the State is unable to reasonably impose its will on armed groups. It is this factor which distinguishes NSAGs from other entities - such as PMSCs – that exist within the State’s normal legal framework. It is this factor that also necessitates international regulation - precisely because the entity cannot be subject to the State's normal rule of law mechanisms.

With respect to a potential legal vacuum. Of course, LoAC establishes essential protections. However, I believe that the biggest gap in LoAC protection relates to the relationship between armed groups and those subject to their influence/control; i.e. it does not regulate how armed groups should treat populations in general (as distinct from treatment of detainees, etc.). De facto authority is something I address in detail, but the short answer is that de facto authorities are traditionally regarded as very established (almost State-like) entities. While some armed groups definitely meet these criteria, many do not. It is this gap, between both the applicability and content of the law of NIAC, and regulation outside NIAC (which will only be required in relatively limited circumstances) that results in a vacuum.

I believe that some of your other questions will be addressed in the coming discussion, and so won’t anticipate that.